The Problem with Instant Runoff Voting
Instant Runoff Voting (IRV) has been
officially endorsed by several organizations and is gaining
momentum. Unfortunately, however, confusion reigns regarding its
advantages and disadvantages. IRV is very good at preventing minor
parties from interfering with the two-party system, but it is arguably
no better than our current plurality system at expanding the two-party
system and giving other parties a chance to actually win
elections. Furthermore, if a third party ever does become strong enough
under IRV to seriously threaten the two major parties, they could hurt
their own cause and wreak havoc with our entire political system, just
as they could under our current plurality system.
IRV can prevent the spoiler effect, in which a minor party splits the
vote with a major party and tilts the election toward the other
major party, hurting its own cause. IRV therefore seems to allow
supporters of minor parties to cast protest votes without "wasting"
their votes. This advantage is illusory, however, because it applies
only as long as those minor parties are sure to lose. As soon
as one of those minor parties threatens to become a major party and
actually win, its supporters vote for them at the risk of hurting their
own cause, just as in the current plurality system. Under IRV, votes for
minor parties are therefore symbolic at best, or dangerous at worst. An
example will illustrate why.
Suppose my true preference is for the Libertarian first and the
Republican second. Suppose further that the Libertarians are the
strongest "minor" party. At some round of the IRV counting process, all
the candidates will be eliminated except the Republican, the Democrat,
and the Libertarian. If the Libertarian then has the fewest first-choice
votes, he or she will be eliminated and my vote will transfer to the
Republican, just as I wanted. But what if the Republican is eliminated
before the Libertarian? Unless all the Republican votes
transfer to the Libertarian, which is extremely unlikely, the Democrat
might then beat the Libertarian. If so, I will have helped the Democrat
win by not strategically ranking the Republican first. But that's the
same situation I'm in now if I vote my true preference for the
Libertarian!
What happened in the above example is that IRV essentially ignored
one of my key preferences. By voting (Libertarian, Republican, ...,
Democrat), I increase the chances that the Republican will be eliminated
before the Libertarian. If that then happens, my preference for the
Republican over the Democrat is essentially discarded or ignored. This
is the fundamental problem with IRV. The only preference that is sure to
be counted is my first choice. The problem gets worse as the number of
candidates increases. The outcome of the election can depend in a very
quirky way on the order in which candidates are eliminated for having
the fewest top-choice votes. The only way a voter can be assured of not
wasting his or her vote is to rank one of the two major parties as their
first choice, which is precisely what happens now under plurality
voting.
The example is hardly contrived. The "lesser of two evils" problem is
almost guaranteed to rear its ugly head again under IRV. Until a minor
party is strong enough to win, a first-choice vote for them is
essentially only symbolic. After a minor party is strong enough
to win, on the other hand, a vote for them could have the same spoiler
effect that it could have under the current plurality system. Hence, if
IRV is ever actually adopted, we will likely remain stuck in the old
two-party system, just as Australia still is, despite the fact that it
has used IRV since around 1920. On the other hand, if minor parties do
somehow manage to become competitive under IRV, they could wreak havoc
with our entire system of government. As in our current system, the
stronger a minor party becomes, the more it could hurt its own
cause.
In other words, IRV can have either of two completely opposite
effects, depending on whether a third party is truly competitive or not.
Before a third party is competitive, the effect of IRV is
equivalent to a plurality system in which all supporters of minor
parties are somehow convinced to abandon their principles and vote for
the "lesser of two evils." Yes, those voters get the satisfaction of
knowing they voted for the party and the candidate they truly prefer,
but their first choice is eventually eliminated and has no effect on who
actually wins. After a third party is competitive, on the other
hand, the effect if IRV is equivalent to a plurality system in which
many voters are somehow convinced to forget about strategy and vote
sincerely. As most intelligent voters know, that would wreak havoc with
the stability of our political system.
IRV has been said to make strategic or defensive voting very
difficult. But strategic voting is difficult under IRV only
after more than two parties are truly competitive. Before that
time, strategic voting is essentially the same as what it is in our
current plurality system: rank the "lesser of two evils" candidate as
your first choice. As soon as more than two parties are truly
competitive, strategic voting could indeed become very difficult because
the "lesser of two evils" concept no longer applies when more than two
parties are competitive. However, this difficulty, far from being an
advantage, is actually a huge disadvantage. Voters will then
need to vote strategically but will be unable to figure out how
to do so, except to revert back to the old two-party paradigm. Hence the
original duopoly will remain intact. In other words, IRV will not solve
the classic "lesser of two evils" problem that plagues plurality
voting.
IRV does have one possible advantage over our current plurality
system: it could be a step toward true electoral reform in the form of
Condorcet voting, which is far superior to IRV. The actual voting
mechanics of IRV and Condorcet voting are identical. In both IRV and
Condorcet voting, the voters rank the candidates, and the required
voting equipment is the same for each. The only difference is the actual
algorithm (and its implementation software) for determining the
winner. In other words, the "front end" is common for IRV and Condorcet
voting, and only the "back end" is different. From a purely technical
perspective, that "back end" software would be very easy to replace, but
the political perspective is another story altogether, of course. If IRV
is widely adopted, it could be transitional to true reform -- or it
could become entrenched.
IRV has other serious problems too, which are explained in more
detail elsewhere at the website. It is an
erratic voting system because ranking a candidate higher can
actually cause the candidate to lose, and ranking a candidate
lower can cause the candidate to win. As if that
weren't bad enough, it can also fail to elect a candidate who is
preferred over each of the other candidates by a majority of the
voters. It is also much more difficult to implement with security and
integrity because the votes cannot be summed as in most other election
methods.
In summary, IRV is a deceptive and potentially dangerous non-reform
masquerading as a reform. If adopted, the cure could be worse than the
disease. Once the inadequacy of IRV becomes clear in actual practice, it
could disillusion the public with electoral reform and thereby close the
door to true reform. The stakes are way too high to get this one
wrong. We can only hope that the well-intentioned and devoted advocates
of IRV are still open-minded enough to recognize this reality. The
battle for electoral reform will be difficult enough without
insurmountable ignorance within the reform movement itself.
Reply to an IRV Advocate
Why IRV is
Ill-Conceived
ElectionMethods.org |